This reconstruction, which merges subject and predicate in one
expression, in order to combine it with the verb of existence,
is repeated in similar proposals of recent English logicians.
Venn, in his Symbolic Logic, proposes the four forms, xȳ = 0,
xy = 0, xy > 0, xȳ > 0 (where ȳ means “not-y”), but only as
alternative to the ordinary forms. Bradley says that “‘S-P
is real’ attributes S-P, directly or indirectly, to the ultimate
reality,” and agrees with Brentano that “’is’ never stands for
anything but ‘exists’”; while Bosanquet, who follows Bradley,
goes so far as to define a categorical judgment as “that which
affirms the existence of its subject, or, in other words, asserts
a fact.” Now it is true that our primary judgments do contain
a belief in existence; but they do not all contain it in the same
way, but are beliefs sometimes that something is determined as
existing, and sometimes that something existing is particularly
determined. Brentano’s forms do not express such a judgment
of existence, as “All existing men are mortal”: nor does
Bradley’s form, “Reality includes S-P.” Metaphysically, all
realities are parts of one ultimate reality; but logically, even
philosophers think more often only of finite realities, existing
men, dogs, horses, &c.; and children know that their parents
exist long before they apprehend ultimate reality. The normal
form, then, of a judgment of existence is either “S is a real P,”
or “A real S is P.” Hence the reconstruction of all categorical
judgments by merging subject and predicate, either on Brentano’s
or on Bradley’s plan, is a misrepresentation even of normal
categorical judgments of existence. Secondly, it is much more
a misrepresentation of categorical judgments of non-existence.
No existential form suits a judgment such as “A centaur is a
fiction,” when we do not believe that there is a centaur, or that
reality includes a centaur. As Mill pointed out, it cannot be
implied that a centaur exists, since the very thing asserted is
that the thing has no real existence. In a correspondence with
Mill, Brentano rejoined that the centaur exists in imagination;
Bradley says, “inside our heads.” According to one, then,
the judgment becomes “There is an imaginary centaur”;
according to the other “Reality includes an imaginary centaur.”
The rejoinder, however, though partly true, is not to the point.
The idea of the centaur does exist in our imagination, and inside
our heads, and the name of it in our mouths. But the point is
that the centaur conceived and named does not exist beyond the
idea of it and the name for it; it is not, like a man, a real thing
which is neither the idea of it nor the name for it. No amount of
subtlety will remove the difference between a categorical judgment
of existence, e.g. “An existing man is mortal,” and a
categorical judgment of non-existence, e.g. “A conceivable
centaur is a fiction,” because in the former we believe and mean
that the thing exists beyond the idea, and in the latter we do
not. If, contrary to usage, we choose to call the latter a judgment
of existence, there is no use in quarrelling about words;
but we must insist that new terms must in that case be invented
to express so fundamental a difference as that between judgments
about real men and judgments about ideal centaurs.
So long, however, as we use words in the natural sense, and call
the former judgments of existence, and the latter judgments of
non-existence, then “is” will not be, as Bradley supposes, the
same as “exists,” for we use “is” in both judgments, but
“exists” only in the first kind. Bosanquet’s definition of a
categorical judgment contains a similar confusion. To assert
a fact and to affirm the existence of a subject are not, as he
makes out, the same thing: a judgment often asserts a fact and
denies existence in the same breath, e.g. “Jupiter is non-existent.”
Here, as usual in logic, tradition is better than innovation.
All categorical judgment is an unconditional belief in the
fact, signified by the copula, that a thing of some sort is (or is
not) determined; but some categorical judgments are also
beliefs that the thing is an existing thing, signified either by the
subject or by the predicate, while others are not beliefs that the
thing exists at all, but are only beliefs in something conceivable,
or nameable, or in something or other, without particularizing
what. Judgment then always signifies being, but not always
existence.
3. Particular and Universal Judgments.—Aristotle, by distinguishing
affirmative and negative, particular and universal,
made the fourfold classification of judgments, A, E, I and O,
the foundation both of opposition and of inference. With regard
to inference, he remarked that a universal judgment means by
“all,” not every individual we know, but every individual
absolutely, so that, when it becomes a major premise, we know
therein every individual universally, not individually, and often
do not know a given individual individually until we add a
minor premise in a syllogism. Whereas, then, a particular
judgment is a belief that some, a universal judgment is a belief
that all, the individuals of a kind or total of similar individuals,
are similarly determined, whether they are known or unknown
individuals. Now, as we have already seen, what is signified by
the subject may be existing or not, and in either case a judgment
remains categorical so long as it is a belief without conditions.
Thus, “Some existing men are poets,” “All existing men are
mortal,” “Some conceivable centaurs are human in their forequarters,”
“All conceivable centaurs are equine in their hindquarters,”
are all categorical judgments, while the two first
are also categorical judgments of existence. Nevertheless these
obvious applications of Aristotelian traditions have been recently
challenged, especially by Sigwart, who holds in his Logic (secs.
27, 36) that, while a particular is a categorical judgment of
existence, a universal is hypothetical, on the ground that it
does not refer to a definite number of individuals, or to individuals
at all, but rather to general ideas, and that the appropriate
form of “all M is P” is “if anything is M it is P.” This
view, which has influenced not only German but also English
logicians, such as Venn, Bradley and Bosanquet, destroys the
fabric of inference, and reduces scientific laws to mere hypotheses.
In reality, however, particular and universal judgments are too
closely connected to have such different imports. In opposition,
a categorical particular is the contradictory of a universal,
which is also categorical, not hypothetical, e.g., “not all M is P”
is the contradictory of “all M is P,” not of “if anything is M it is
P.” In inference, a particular is an example of a universal which
in its turn may become a particular example of a higher universal.
For instance, in the history of mechanics it was first inferred
from some that all terrestrial bodies gravitate, and then from
these as some that all ponderable bodies, terrestrial and celestial,
gravitate. How absurd to suppose that here we pass from a
particular categorical to a universal hypothetical, and then treat
this very conclusion as a particular categorical to pass to a higher
universal hypothetical! Sigwart, indeed, is deceived both about
particulars and universals. On the one hand, some particulars
are not judgments of existence, e.g. “some imaginary deities
are goddesses”; on the other hand, some universals are not
judgments of non-existence, e.g. “every existing man is mortal.”
Neither kind is always a judgment of existence, but each is sometimes
the one and sometimes the other. In no case is a universal
hypothetical, unless we think it under a condition; for in a
universal judgment about the non-existing, e.g. about all conceivable
centaurs, we do not think, “If anything is a centaur,”
because we do not believe that there are any; and in a universal
judgment about the existent, e.g. about all existing men, we do
not think, “If anything is a man,” because we believe that there
is a whole class of men existing at different times and places.
The cause of Sigwart’s error is his misconception of “all.” So
far as he follows Aristotle in saying that “all” does not mean
a definite number of individuals he is right; but when he says
that we mean no individuals at all he deserts Aristotle and goes
wrong. By “all” we mean every individual whatever of a kind;
and when from the experience of sense and memory we start
with particular judgments of existence, and infer universal
judgments of existence and scientific laws, we further mean those
existing individuals which we have experienced, and every
individual whatever of the kind which exists. We mean neither
a definite number of individuals, nor yet an infinite number, but
an incalculable number, whether experienced or inferred to
exist. We do not mean existing here and now, nor yet out of
time and place, but at any time and place (semper et ubique)—past,
Page:EB1911 - Volume 16.djvu/910
Jump to navigation
Jump to search
888
LOGIC
[JUDGMENT