died in London on the 5th of August 1858. Soyer was the inventor of an army cooking wagon, and the author of a variety of cookery books. His wife, Elizabeth Emma Soyer, achieved considerable popularity as a painter, chiefly of portraits.
SOZOMEN, the name of a famous 5th-century church historian. Hermias Salamanes (Salaminius) Sozomenus (c. 400–443) came of a wealthy family of Palestine, and it is exceedingly
probable that he himself was born and brought up there—in
Gaza or the neighbourhood. What he has to tell us of the
history of South Palestine was derived from oral tradition.
His grandfather, he tells us, lived at Bethel, near Gaza, and
became a Christian, probably under Constantius, through the
influence of Hilarion, who had miraculously healed an acquaintance of the grandfather, one Alaphion. Both men with
their families became zealous Christians. The historian’s
grandfather became within his own circle a highly esteemed
interpreter of Scripture, and held fast his profession even in
the time of Julian. The descendants of the wealthy Alaphion
founded churches and convents in the district, and were particularly active in promoting monasticism. Sozomen himself
had conversed with one of these, a very old man. He tells us
that he was brought up under monkish influences and his history
bears him out. As a man he retained the impressions of his
youth, and his great work was to be also a monument of his
reverence for the monks in general and for the disciples of
Hilarion in particular. After studying law in Beirut he settled
down as an advocate in Constantinople, where he wrote his
Εκκλησιαστική Ἱστορία about the year 440. The nine
books of which it is composed begin with Constantine (323)
and come down to the death of Honorius (423); but according
to his own statement he intended to continue it as far as the
year 439 (see the Dedication of the work). From Sozomen
himself (iv. 17), and statements of his excerptors Nicephorus
and Theophanes, it can be made out that the work did actually
come down to that year, and that consequently it has reached us
only in a mutilated condition, at least half a book being wanting
(Güldenpenning, Theodoros von Kyrrhos, p. 12 seq., holds that
Sozomen himself suppressed the end of his work). A flattering and bombastic dedication to Theodosius II. is prefixed.
When compared with the history of the ecclesiastical historian
Socrates (q.v.), it is plainly seen to be a plagiarism from that
work, and that on a large scale. Some three-fourths of the
materials, essentially in the same arrangement, have been
appropriated from his predecessor without his being named,
the other sources to which Sozomen was indebted being expressly
cited. But it is to his credit that he has been himself at the
trouble to refer to the principal sources used by Socrates
(Rufinus, Eusebius, Athanasius, Sabinus, the collections of
epistles, Palladius), and has not unfrequently supplemented
Socrates from them; and also that he has used some new
authorities, in particular sources relating to Christianity in
Persia and to the history of Arianism, monkish histories,
the Vita Martini of Sulpicius, and works of Hilarius. The
whole of the ninth book is drawn from Olympiodorus.
It is probable that Sozomen did not approve of Socrates’s freer attitude towards Greek science, and that he wished to present a picture in which the clergy should be still further glorified and monasticism brought into still stronger pro- minence. In Sozomen everything is a shade more ecclesiastical—but only a shade—than in Socrates. Perhaps also he wrote for the monks in Palestine, and could be sure that the work of his predecessor would not be known.
Sozomen is an inferior Socrates. What in Socrates still betrays some vestiges of historical sense, his moderation, his reserve in questions of dogma, his impartiality—all this is wanting in Sozomen. In many cases he has repeated the exact words of Socrates, but with him they have passed almost into mere phrases. The chronological scrupulosity of the earlier writer has made no impression on his follower; he has either wholly omitted or inaccurately repeated the chronological data. He writes more wordily and diffusely. In his characterizations of persons, borrowed from Socrates, he is more dull and colourless. After Socrates he has indeed repeated the caution not to be too rash in discerning the finger of God; but his way of looking at things is throughout mean and rustic. Two souls inhabit his book; one, the better, is borrowed from Socrates; another, the worse, is his own. Evidence of a boundless credulity with regard to all sorts of monkish fables is to be met with everywhere. It must, however, be noted that for the period from Theodosius I. onward he has emancipated himself more fully from Socrates and has followed Olympiodorus in part, partly also oral tradition; and here his statements possess greater value.
Sozomen also wrote an Epitome of History from the Ascension of Christ to the defeat of Licinius (323) which is not now extant (see his History, i. 1).
For bibliography see the article on the church historian, Socrates. Most of the editions and discussions named there cover Sozomen as well (the volume of Hussey’s edition containing Sozomen appeared in 1860). The latest English translation, revised by Hartranft, is published in the Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, 2nd series, vol. ii. In addition see Nolte in the Tübing. Quartalschr. (1861), p. 417 sqq.; C. de Boor, " Zur Kenntniss der Handschriften der Griech. Kirchenhistoriker," in Zeitschrift für Kirchengeschichte, vi. 478 sqq.; Sarrazin, " De Sozomeni historia num integra sit," in the Commentationes philologae jenenses, i. 165 sqq.; Rosenstein, " Krit. Untersuchungen über d. Verhaltniss zwischen Olympiodor, Zosimus und Sozomen," in Forsch. z. deutschen Gesch., vol. i. ; Batiffol, "Sozomène et Sabinos," in Byzant. Zeitschr. vii. 265 sqq. (A. Ha.; A. C. McG.)
SPA, a town, of Belgium, lying less than 20 m. S.E. of Liége
and in the same province, famous for its mineral springs, which
are reputed to be the oldest known in Europe, having been
first discovered in 1326. They are supposed to have given the
common name of “spa” to such resorts. The town is situated
850 ft. above sea-level and the heights above the valley reach
1100 ft. In the 18th century it was the most fashionable resort
in Europe for the medicinal use of such waters, being visited
by Peter the Great of Russia, Gustavus III. of Sweden, and
Joseph II. of Austria. In 1807 much of the town was burned
down, while the principal buildings, the Casino and the Pouhon,
are quite modern. Spa has not held its own with its many
French and German rivals, but it still attracts about 20,000
visitors annually. Pop. (1904), 7759.
SPACE AND TIME, in philosophy. The metaphysical problems connected with Space and Time are so similar and have been so closely conjoined in the history of thought that they may well be treated together. They are clearly distinguishable from the psychological, which relate to the modes whereby our spatial and temporal conceptions have been formed and to the analysis of the materials of which they are composed (see Psychology). In an exhaustive treatment of Space and Time by far the largest share of the work rests with the psychologist. The business of the metaphysician is to determine what reality outside our minds corresponds to our temporal and spatial conceptions.
The first tendency of thought is to treat Space and Time as having objective existence in the same way as the ordinary things that compose our world, and this we may call the objective method. Simple as it appears to be, it discloses formidable difficulties, which may be illustrated by a consideration of Newton’s famous account of “absolute, true and mathematical time” as something which “in itself and from its own nature flows equally” and with no liability to change. Now, if mathematical time as thus described is merely an abstraction used to facilitate mathematical calculations, no objection can be taken to it. But if Newton meant to assert that Time is a flowing stream no less actual than the Thames, his assertion is open to fatal objections. All admittedly real streams, such as the Thames, have a definite beginning and an ending. But where is the source of Time and where is its outlet? Every real stream has boundaries at its sides. What are the boundaries of Time? Every real stream has certain definite qualities: water is rather heavy and translucent, and produces certain effects upon bodies plunged into it. What are the specific qualities of Time? How are things in time affected by their immersion in time so as to be different from things not in time? And if it be asserted that time has such specific qualities, by what senses do we perceive them? We may fairly assume that none of these questions can be answered intelligibly by one who holds the Newtonian position. And thus we are justified in the conclusion that time is not a real