Page:Obergefell v. Hodges.pdf/73

From Wikisource
Jump to navigation Jump to search
This page has been proofread, but needs to be validated.
Cite as: 576 U. S. ___ (2015)
5

Scalia, J., dissenting

dimensions….”[1] One would think that sentence would continue: “…and therefore they provided for a means by which the People could amend the Constitution,” or perhaps “…and therefore they left the creation of additional liberties, such as the freedom to marry someone of the same sex, to the People, through the never-ending process of legislation.” But no. What logically follows, in the majority’s judge-empowering estimation, is: “and so they entrusted to future generations a charter protecting the right of all persons to enjoy liberty as we learn its meaning.”[2] The “we,” needless to say, is the nine of us. “History and tradition guide and discipline [our] inquiry but do not set its outer boundaries.”[3] Thus, rather than focusing on the People’s understanding of “liberty”–at the time of ratification or even today–the majority focuses on four “principles and traditions” that, in the majority’s view, prohibit States from defining marriage as an institution consisting of one man and one woman.[4]

This is a naked judicial claim to legislative–indeed, super-legislative–power; a claim fundamentally at odds with our system of government. Except as limited by a constitutional prohibition agreed to by the People, the States are free to adopt whatever laws they like, even those that offend the esteemed Justices’ “reasoned judgment.” A system of government that makes the People subordinate to a committee of nine unelected lawyers does not deserve to be called a democracy.

Judges are selected precisely for their skill as lawyers; whether they reflect the policy views of a particular constituency is not (or should not be) relevant. Not surprisingly then, the Federal Judiciary is hardly a cross-section

  1. Ante, at 11.
  2. Ibid.
  3. Ante, at 10, 11.
  4. Ante, at 12, 18.