Philosophical Works of the Late James Frederick Ferrier/Institutes of Metaphysic (1875)
Appearance
INSTITUTES OF METAPHYSIC
THE
THEORY OF KNOWING AND BEING
BY
J. F. FERRIER, A.B., OXON.
PROFESSOR OP MORAL PHILOSOPHY AND POLITICAL ECONOMY,
ST ANDREWS
THIRD EDITION
WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS
EDINBURGH AND LONDON
MDCCCLXXV
CONTENTS.
PAGE | ||
INTRODUCTION. | ||
1. | The word "Philosophy" as here employed, | 1 |
2. | The two main requisitions of philosophy, | 1 |
3. | Which of them is the more stringent, | 2 |
4. | The value of systems determined by a reference to these requisitions | 2 |
5. | An unreasoned system of no value, because at variance with definition of philosophy, | 3 |
6. | Because, though true, it cannot be certain, | 3 |
7. | Because of no use as a mental discipline, | 3 |
8. | A reasoned system, though not true, has some value as an exercise of reason, | 4 |
9. | It complies more closely with definition of philosophy than the other, | 4 |
10. | But a system should be both true and reasoned, | 5 |
11. | Systems of philosophy are unreasoned hitherto, | 5 |
12. | The present state of philosophy described, | 6 |
13. | First, How is this state to be explained? Secondly, How remedied? | 7 |
14. | First, it is explained (§§ 14–31) by philosophy not being reasoned, | 8 |
15. | No good can be expected so long as philosophy is not reasoned, | 8 |
16. | The masks of philosophy, | 9 |
17. | Its unsatisfactory state further accounted for. The globe of speculation, | 11 |
18. | Explanation continued. First principles always come out last, | 12 |
19. | Illustrations of this from language and grammar, | 13 |
20. | Illustration continued, | 14 |
21. | Illustration from logic, | 15 |
22. | Illustration from law, | 15 |
23. | Application to philosophy. Here, too, first principles come out last, | 16 |
24. | These principles, though operative in philosophy, are unnoticed and unknown, | 17 |
25. | Hence philosophy is nowhere a scheme reasoned throughout, | 18 |
26. | The repudiation of necessary truths, a further retarding cause, | 19 |
27. | What necessary truth is, . | 20 |
28. | Its criterion is "the law of contradiction." Law explained, | 21 |
29. | Its criterion is not ready acceptance, | 22 |
30. | Return. Philosophy deals with necessary truths—therefore retarded by their prescription, | 23 |
31. | How ill the necessary truths hare fared in Germany and in our own country, | 24 |
32. | Secondly, How is the unsatisfactory state of philosophy to be remedied? Short answer, | 26 |
33. | A remedial system uniting truth and reason, not impossible, | 28 |
34. | Single canon for the right use of reason, | 28 |
35. | This system of Institutes claims both truth and demonstration, but rather demonstration than truth, | 29 |
36. | It is a body of necessary truth. Its pretensions stated, | 30 |
37. | An objection to its method stated and obviated, | 31 |
38. | The polemical character of this system, | 31 |
39. | Why philosophy must be polemical. She exists only to correct the inadvertencies of ordinary thinking, | 32 |
40. | This might be abundantly proved by the testimony of philosophers, | 33 |
41. | The object (or business to do) of philosophy renders her essentially polemical, | 33 |
42. | The charge of disrespect which might be supposed to attach to philosophy on account of her polemical character, obviated, | 34 |
43. | This system also adverse to psychology—and why, | 34 |
44. | What philosophy has to do, again distinctly stated, | 36 |
45. | Its positive object still more distinctly stated. Definition of metaphysics, | 36 |
46. | Why philosophy undertakes this object, | 38 |
47. | How philosophy goes to work. Adherence to canon—proposition and counter-proposition, | 38 |
48. | Further explanations as to how philosophy goes to work, | 40 |
49. | Advantages of this method, | 41 |
50. | Disadvantages of not contrasting distinctly the true and the false, | 41 |
51. | General unintelligibility of systems is due to their neglect to exhibit this contrast, | 42 |
52. | This system contrasts distinctly the true and the false, | 45 |
53. | The three sections of this institute. Arrangement explained and proved to be essential (§§ 54-62), | 46 |
54. | The section called ontology naturally comes first,—but is truly last in order, | 46 |
55. | It must be made to revolve away from us, in order to bring round the epistemology, which, though it naturally comes last, is truly first in order, | 47 |
56. | Epistemology and ontology the two main divisions of philosophy, | 49 |
57. | The epistemology does of itself afford no entrance to ontology. Why not?, | 49 |
58. | Because "Absolute Existence" may be that which we are ignorant of, | 50 |
59. | This consideration necessitates a new section of philosophy called the agnoiology. Its business, | 50 |
60. | Now we can settle the problem of ontology—and how, | 51 |
61. | Recapitulation of the three sections. 1. Epistemology. 2. Agnoiology. 3. Ontology. This arrangement not arbitrary, but necessary, | 52 |
62. | The necessity of keeping these divisions perfectly distinct, | 52 |
63. | The natural oversights of thought are rectified in these three sections, | 53 |
64. | Remarks obviating any objections to the system, on the ground that its conclusions cannot at all times be present to the mind, | 54 |
65. | Continuation of these remarks, | 56 |
66. | Remark obviating any objection to this system on the score of presumption, | 58 |
67. | The indispensable extension of the necessary laws to all reason, | 59 |
68. | An objection to the system on the score of inconsistency obviated, | 60 |
69. | Objection retorted. The confusion of philosophers in regard to the conceivable and the inconceivable, | 61 |
70. | This confusion illustrated, | 62 |
71. | All other systems make game of the laws of thought, | 63 |
72. | The inconsistency of philosophers inextricable, | 64 |
73. | Their laws of thought always turn out, at best, to be mere laws of imagination, | 65 |
74. | This system does not make game of the laws of thought, | 66 |
75. | It abridges the grounds of controversy, | 66 |
76. | Conclusion of introduction explaining how the starting-point of philosophy is reached (§§ 76-85), | 67 |
77. | How the starting-point is reached, | 67 |
78. | Plato, in Theætetus, fails to reach the starting-point, | 68 |
79. | Search for the starting-point, | 69 |
80. | Why the question—What is knowledge? cannot be the starting-point, | 71 |
81. | This question resolved into two questions, | 72 |
82. | Which of them is our question,—and the first in philosophy, | 72 |
83. | That philosophy has a starting-point proved by the fact that its starting-point has been found, | 73 |
84. | Starting-point must state the essential of knowledge. Experience may confirm, but reason alone can establish its truth, | 74 |
85. | Re-statement of the first or proximate question of philosophy, | 74 |
86. | Its answer is the absolute starting-point, and forms the first proposition of these Institutes, | 75 |
SECTION I. | ||
THE EPISTEMOLOGY, OR THEORY OF KNOWING. | ||
PROPOSITION I. | ||
The Primary Law or Condition of All Knowledge, | 79 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 79 | |
1. | Prop. I. answers the first question of philosophy, | 79 |
2. | It expresses the most general and essential law of all knowledge, | 80 |
3. | It declares that self-consciousness is never entirely suspended when the mind knows anything, | 81 |
4. | Objection that self-consciousness seems at times to be extinct, | 81 |
5. | Objection obviated. Proposition explained, | 81 |
6. | Our apparent inattention to self accounted for by the principle of familiarity, | 82 |
7. | Also by the consideration that the ego is no object of sensible experience, | 84 |
8. | A theory of self-consciousness at variance with Prop. I. refuted, | 85 |
9. | Importance of Prop. I. as foundation of the whole system, | 86 |
10. | It is not refuted but rather confirmed by experience, | 87 |
11. | Its best evidence is reason, which fixes it as a necessary truth or axiom, | 87 |
12. | First Counter-proposition, | 89 |
13. | It embodies the result of ordinary thinking and of popular psychology, | 89 |
14. | It is generally the starting-point of psychology, as Prop. I. is the starting-point of metaphysics, | 90 |
15. | A mark of distinction between the propositions and the counter-propositions, | 91 |
16. | Prop. I. has some affinity to Pythagorean doctrine of numbers, | 92 |
17. | Misunderstanding as to Pythagorean doctrine, | 93 |
18. | Prop. I. a higher generalisation of the Pythagorean law, | 94 |
19. | Anticipations of Prop. I. by the philosophers of Germany, | 94 |
PROPOSITION II. | ||
The Object of All Knowledge, | 97 | |
Demonstration, | 97 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 98 | |
1. | Reason for printing "itself-in-union-with-whatever-it-apprehends" as one word, | 98 |
2. | By the object of knowledge is meant the whole object of knowledge, | 99 |
3. | Change which an attention to the condition of knowledge effects upon the object of knowledge, | 100 |
4. | Further illustrated by the speculative, as distinguished from the ordinary mode of enumeration, | 100 |
5. | Second Counter-proposition, | 101 |
6. | It is false, because Counter-proposition I. is false, | 102 |
7. | It expresses the ordinary notion, and also, generally, the psychological opinion as to the object of knowledge, | 103 |
PROPOSITION III. | ||
The Inseparability of the Objective and the Subjective, | 105 | |
Demonstration, | 105 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 106 | |
1. | Reasons for giving this proposition a prominent place in the system, | 106 |
2. | What is meant by separability and inseparability in cognition, | 107 |
3. | A possible misapprehension obviated, | 108 |
4. | Inseparability in cognition not to be confounded with inseparability in space: the external and the internal, | 109 |
5. | The unit of cognition explained. How it is determined, | 110 |
6. | Importance of the words "by itself," or per se, | 111 |
7. | The unit of cognition further explained, | 112 |
8. | No essential but only an accidental difference between the minimum and the maximum of cognition, | 112 |
9. | Third Counter-proposition, | 113 |
10. | It embodies an inadvertency of natural thinking, | 113 |
11. | The psychological position more false and ambiguous than the natural inadvertency, | 114 |
12. | The psychological error accounted for, | 115 |
13. | Distinction of science of mind and science of matter characterised, | 115 |
14. | Invalidity of counter-proposition III. Its origin, §§ 14, 15, 16, 17, | 116 |
15. | Many things are distinguishable, which are not separable, in cognition, | 117 |
16. | Illustrations applied to subject and object., | 118 |
17. | Further illustration, | 118 |
18. | Short statement of what this proposition contends for, | 119 |
19. | No opinion offered as to existence, | 120 |
PROPOSITION IV. | ||
Matter per se, | 121 | |
Demonstration, | 121 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 122 | |
1. | Idealism and materialism have their roots here, | 122 |
2. | Fourth Counter-proposition, | 122 |
3. | It expresses common opinion as to our knowledge of matter per se, | 122 |
4. | Oversight of self only apparent—not real and total, | 123 |
5. | Psychological opinion as to our knowledge of matter per se, | 123 |
6. | Psychological materialism as founded on the four counter-propositions, | 124 |
7. | Fallacy of materialism. Possibility of idealism as founded on the four propositions, | 125 |
8. | A preliminary question prejudged by materialist and by idealist, | 126 |
9. | Cause of this precipitate judgment. Its evil consequences, | 127 |
10. | How Prop. IV. decides this preliminary question. How Counter-proposition IV. decides it, | 128 |
11. | Symbols illustrative of the position maintained by the Institutes, | 128 |
12. | The same symbols as illustrative of the psychological position, | 129 |
13. | Different conclusions from the two positions, | 130 |
14. | Difference farther explained, | 131 |
15. | Another point of difference between this system and psychology, | 132 |
16. | Matter per se reduced to the contradictory, | 134 |
17. | This contradiction attaches not only to our knowledge of matter per se, | 136 |
18. | But to matter per se itself, | 137 |
19. | Advantage of this reduction. New light on the problem of philosophy, | 139 |
20. | Importance of finding the contradictory, | 140 |
21. | In what sense the contradictory is conceivable, | 141 |
22. | Matter per se is not a nonentity, | 142 |
PROPOSITION V. | ||
Matter and its Qualities per se, | 144 | |
Demonstration, | 144 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 144 | |
1. | Why Proposition V. is introduced, | 144 |
2. | Fifth Counter-proposition, | 145 |
3. | Distinction between the primary and the secondary qualities of matter, | 146 |
4. | Character of the secondary qualities, | 146 |
5. | Character of the primary qualities, | 148 |
6. | Defects of this distinction, | 149 |
7. | It runs into a contradiction, | 151 |
8. | Psychological conception of idealism, | 151 |
9. | Psychological refutation of idealism, | 152 |
10. | This refutation, if logically conclusive, is founded on a contradiction and therefore cannot be accepted, | 154 |
11. | The distinction of the primary and secondary qualities should be abandoned as useless, or worse, | 155 |
PROPOSITION VI. | ||
The Universal and the Particular in Cognition, | 156 | |
Demonstration, | 157 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 157 | |
1. | Explanation of words, | 158 |
2. | In what sense the contingent element is necessary, and in what sense it is contingent, | 158 |
3. | Why this proposition is introduced, | 160 |
4. | Question concerning the particular and the universal instead of being made a question of Knowing, | 161 |
5. | Was made a question of being by the early philosophers. Thales, | 163 |
6. | Parmenides. What change he effected on the question, | 163 |
7. | It still related to Being—not to Knowing, | 164 |
8. | Indecision of Greek speculation. The three crises of philosophy, | 165 |
9. | Plato appeared during the second crisis. His aim, | 167 |
10. | The coincidence of the known and the existent must be proved, not guessed at, | 168 |
11. | Plato's deficiencies, | 168 |
12. | His merits. The question respecting the particular and the universal demands an entire reconsideration, | 169 |
13. | A preliminary ambiguity, | 170 |
14. | Further statement of ambiguity, | 171 |
15. | Illustration of the ambiguity, | 171 |
16. | Is the Platonic analysis of cognition and existence a division into elements or into kinds?, | 173 |
17. | Rightly interpreted, it is a division into elements, | 174 |
18. | It has been generally mistaken for a division into kinds, | 176 |
19. | Explanation of this charge, | 177 |
20. | Sixth Counter-proposition, | 179 |
21. | This counter-proposition is itself a proof of the charge here made against philosophers, | 180 |
22. | Review of our position, | 181 |
23. | Misinterpretation of the Platonic analysis traced into its consequences, | 182 |
24. | Perplexity as to general existences, | 183 |
25. | Realism, | 183 |
26. | Realism is superseded by Conceptualism, | 184 |
27. | Conceptualism is destroyed by Nominalism, | 185 |
28. | Evasion by which conceptualism endeavours to recover her ground, and to conciliate nominalism. Its failure, | 186 |
29. | Nominalism, | 190 |
30. | Nominalism is annihilated by Proposition VI., | 191 |
31. | The summing up, | 192 |
32. | The abstract and the concrete, | 193 |
PROPOSITION VII. | ||
What the Universal and the Particular in Cognition are, | 196 | |
Demonstration, | 196 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 197 | |
1. | Why this Proposition is introduced, | 197 |
2. | The ego is coextensive with the universal, matter is not coextensive with the particular, element, | 198 |
3. | Another reason for introducing this proposition, | 199 |
4. | Remarkable that this proposition should not have been propounded long ago, | 199 |
5. | The oversight accounted for. Effect of familiarity, | 200 |
6. | We study the strange rather than the familiar, hence truth escapes us, | 202 |
7. | Hence neglect of this proposition, | 204 |
8. | Another circumstance which may have caused the neglect of this proposition, | 206 |
9. | The ego is the summum genus of cognition. Ontological generalisation, | 206 |
10. | Epistemological generalisation is very different, | 207 |
11. | The ego not a mere generalisation from experience, | 209 |
12. | Shortcoming of the Platonic ideas, | 210 |
13. | Perhaps the ego is the summum genus of existence as well as of cognition, | 212 |
14. | The second clause of proposition has had a standing in philosophy from the earliest times, | 213 |
15. | A ground of perplexity, | 213 |
16. | Demur as to matter being the fluctuating in existence, | 214 |
17. | It is certainly the fluctuating in cognition, | 215 |
18. | The old philosophers held it to be both, | 215 |
19. | More attention should have been paid to their assertion that it was the fluctuating in cognition, | 216 |
20. | Matter as the fluctuating in cognition: explained., | 217 |
21. | This is the fluctuation which epistemology attends to, | 217 |
22. | A hint as to its fluctuation in existence, | 218 |
23. | The ego as the non-fluctuating in cognition: explained, | 219 |
24. | Seventh Counter-proposition, | 219 |
25. | Expresses the contradictory inadvertency of ordinary thinking: illustration, | 220 |
26. | Corrective illustration, | 221 |
27. | Psychology adopts Counter-proposition VII., | 222 |
28. | And thereby loses hold of the only argument for immateriality, | 223 |
PROPOSITION VIII. | ||
The Ego in Cognition, | 224 | |
Demonstration, | 224 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 226 | |
1. | A caveat, | 226 |
2. | Important law of knowledge, | 226 |
3. | Materiality and immateriality. Eighth Counter-proposition, | 227 |
4. | Eighth counter-proposition the common property of materialist and spiritualist, | 228 |
5. | Early conception of mind as material. Ghosts, clairvoyance, spirit rapping, | 229 |
6. | Conception of mind as material substance dismissed, | 231 |
7. | Conception of mind as result of organisation: phrenology, | 231 |
8. | The spiritualist's conception of mind is as null as the materialist's, | 232 |
9. | Both parties hold mind to be particular, | 233 |
10. | It is known only as the universal, | 234 |
11. | The materialist's error consists in his holding mind to be particular, | 235 |
12. | The spiritualist's error consists in his holding mind to be particular, | 236 |
13. | The two errors summed up, | 238 |
14. | Recapitulation of the institutional proof of immateriality, | 238 |
PROPOSITION IX. | ||
The Ego per se, | 241 | |
Demonstration, | 241 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 242 | |
1. | Purport of this proposition in relation to Proposition I., | 242 |
2. | An objection started, | 242 |
3. | Objection obviated, | 243 |
4. | Another objection obviated, | 244 |
5. | David Hume outgoes this proposition, | 245 |
6. | What this proposition contends for, | 246 |
7. | The mind must always know itself in, but not as, some determinate condition, | 246 |
8. | Ninth Counter-proposition, | 248 |
9. | Its twofold error, | 248 |
10. | History of word "essence." Its meaning reversed by moderns, | 249 |
11. | Consequences of this reversal—injustice to the old philosophers, | 250 |
12. | Confusion and error to which the reversal has led, | 251 |
13. | This proposition reduces the ego per se to a contradiction, | 252 |
14. | Why the word ego is used in these discussions, | 253 |
15. | The individual or monad, | 253 |
16. | An objection obviated, | 254 |
17. | Another objection obviated, | 255 |
PROPOSITION X. | ||
Sense and Intellect, | 257 | |
Demonstration, | 257 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 258 | |
1. | Comment on data of proof of this proposition, | 258 |
2. | Tenth Counter-proposition, | 259 |
3. | The Leibnitzian restriction of counter-proposition, | 259 |
4. | Comment on the translation here given of the counter-proposition, | 260 |
5. | The counter-proposition is equally contradictory, whether accepted without, or with, a restriction, | 261 |
6. | The counter-proposition is the foundation of "sensualism"—character of sensualism, | 261 |
7. | The anti-sensual psychology merely restricts the counter-proposition—leaves the contradiction uncorrected, | 263 |
8. | The root of the mischief. History of distinction between sense and intellect, | 264 |
9. | Aim and procedure of Greek metaphysics, | 264 |
10. | A rule for the historian of philosophy, | 266 |
11. | This rule observed in these Institutes, | 266 |
12. | Return to history of distinction between sense and intellect, | 267 |
13. | Illustration of early Greek doctrine, | 269 |
14. | The old philosophers were right in their problem—in their way of working it, and in fixing sense as the faculty of nonsense, | 270 |
15. | A reason why the truth of this doctrine is not obvious, | 271 |
16. | Difficulty and difference of opinion as to intellectual element, | 272 |
17. | Ambiguities of the old philosophers, | 273 |
18. | Three misconceptions arising out of these ambiguities, | 273 |
19. | Comment on first misconception, | 275 |
20. | Comment on second misconception, | 276 |
21. | Comment on third misconception, | 277 |
22. | Key to the Greek philosophy, | 279 |
23. | Return to counter-proposition. It is founded on a confusion of the distinction between sense and intellect, | 281 |
24. | The Lockian and the Kantian psychology in limiting the counter-proposition effect no subversion of sensualism, | 282 |
25. | Kant's doctrine impotent against sensualism, | 283 |
26. | The statement in par. 4, and the charge in par. 7, are borne out by the foregoing remarks, | 286 |
27. | Kant sometimes nearly right. He errs through a neglect of necessary truth, | 287 |
28. | The true compromise between Sense and Intellect, | 288 |
PROPOSITION XI. | ||
Presentation and Representation, | 290 | |
Demonstration, | 290 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 291 | |
1. | Why this proposition is introduced, | 291 |
2. | Distinction between knowing and thinking, | 292 |
3. | This proposition the foundation of a true philosophy of experience, | 293 |
4. | Representation—its two insuperable restrictions, | 293 |
5. | First restriction by way of addition. Second by way of subtraction, | 294 |
6. | The latter restriction unrecognised by philosophers. Eleventh Counter-proposition, | 295 |
7. | Its invalidity shown, | 296 |
8. | The minimum cogitable equates with the minimum scibile, | 296 |
9. | Dr Reid's mistake in his assault on representationism, | 297 |
10. | The truth and the error of representationism, | 299 |
PROPOSITION XII. | ||
Matter per se again, | 300 | |
Demonstration, | 300 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 300 | |
1. | Why this proposition is introduced, | 301 |
2. | On what condition matter per se might be thought of, | 302 |
3. | In attempting to think it, we must leave out an element essential to its cognition, and therefore it cannot be thought of, | 303 |
4. | How the imagination leads us astray, | 303 |
5. | Illustration, | 304 |
6. | Self must be represented just as much as it must be presented, | 305 |
7. | Twelfth Counter-proposition, | 305 |
8. | Its character and downfall, | 306 |
9. | Matter per se has no chance of being thought of, | 306 |
10. | It cannot be reached by the way of inference, | 307 |
11. | Why the discussion respecting matter per se is important, | 307 |
PROPOSITION XIII. | ||
The Independent Universe in Thought, | 310 | |
Demonstration, | 310 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 311 | |
1. | This proposition speaks only of what can be conceived, not of what exists, | 311 |
2. | It answers the question—what independent universe can be thought of?, | 311 |
3. | Why we do not think of things as amorphous when they are absent from us, | 312 |
4. | An objection stated, | 313 |
5. | Objection obviated. We have a single type—can suppose it repeated, | 314 |
6. | Why we cannot cogitate matter per se—no single type, | 315 |
7. | We have a single type of objects + subject—can conceive other cases of this, | 315 |
8. | Further explanation of how one self can conceive another self, | 316 |
9. | A word on Belief, | 318 |
10. | Another difficulty obviated, | 318 |
11. | Thirteenth Counter-proposition, | 320 |
PROPOSITION XIV. | ||
The Phenomenal in Cognition, | 321 | |
Demonstration, | 321 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 321 | |
1. | Fourteenth Counter-proposition, | 321 |
2. | A good rule for reaching truth on metaphysical topics, | 322 |
3. | The psychological trifling with truth ought to be put a stop to, | 322 |
4. | The main object of this and three following propositions, | 323 |
PROPOSITION XV. | ||
What the Phenomenal in Cognition is, | 324 | |
Demonstration, | 324 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 325 | |
1. | A peculiarity in the counter-proposition, | 325 |
2. | Fifteenth Counter -proposition, | 326 |
3. | The counter-proposition involves a contradiction, | 326 |
PROPOSITION XVI. | ||
The Substantial in Cognition, | 328 | |
Demonstration, | 328 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 329 | |
1. | This proposition proves nothing as to existing substance, | 329 |
2. | Neither does it declare the nature of known substance, | 329 |
3. | Reasons for introducing this proposition, | 330 |
4. | The position of natural thinking in regard to this proposition, | 331 |
5. | Sixteenth Counter-proposition, | 332 |
6. | Its downfall, | 333 |
7. | Defence of definition of known substance, | 333 |
8. | This definition is due to Spinoza, | 334 |
PROPOSITION XVII. | ||
What the Substantial in Cognition is, | 335 | |
Demonstration, | 335 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 336 | |
1. | Seventeenth Counter-proposition, | 336 |
2. | Conglomerate character of the counter-proposition, | 337 |
3. | Elimination of its ontological surplusage, | 337 |
4. | Its contradictory character exposed in so far as it is psychological, | 339 |
5. | The counter-proposition considered in so far as it is the product of natural thinking, | 340 |
6. | The exact point in the counter-proposition which natural thinking opposes to the proposition, | 341 |
7. | Contradiction in the counter-proposition, in so far as it is the product of natural thinking, | 341 |
8. | Psychological opinion as to existing substance, | 342 |
9. | First, It does not answer its purpose, | 342 |
10. | Secondly, It places before us the mere phenomenal, | 343 |
11. | The institutional conception of known substance, | 344 |
12. | History of distinction between substance and phenomenon—its terms have been reversed, | 345 |
13. | Errors caused by this reversal, | 346 |
14. | Substance and phenomenon originally bore the signification assigned to them here, | 347 |
15. | The known phenomenal according to the older systems, | 348 |
16. | The known substantial according to the older systems, | 348 |
17. | A word upon existing substance and phenomenon, | 349 |
18. | Two main ambiguities in the old systems, | 350 |
19. | These ambiguities accounted for, | 351 |
20. | And cleared up by a reference to the Institutional doctrine, | 352 |
21. | Coincidence of the old speculations with the Institutes, | 353 |
22. | An objection obviated, | 354 |
23. | Mistakes of the historians of philosophy as to substance, | 355 |
24. | A traditional dogma about disdaining the senses, | 356 |
25. | The true meaning of turning the mind away from the senses, | 357 |
26. | What the ancient philosophers meant by this dogma, | 359 |
27. | Contrast between speculation and psychology in their views of substance and phenomenon, | 360 |
28. | Speculation proved to be right even by a reference to experience, | 361 |
PROPOSITION XVIII. | ||
The Relative in Cognition, | 363 | |
Demonstration, | 363 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 363 | |
1. | The same error is continually reappearing under new forms—must be unmasked under all its disguises, | 364 |
2. | Hence the necessity of Props. XVIII., XIX., XX., XXI., | 365 |
3. | Eighteenth Counter-proposition, | 366 |
4. | It is shown to be contradictory, | 366 |
PROPOSITION XIX. | ||
What the Relative in Cognition is, | 367 | |
Demonstration, | 367 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 368 | |
1. | Why the items mentioned in the proposition can be known only as the relative, | 368 |
2. | Nineteenth Counter-proposition, | 368 |
3. | Its fallacy shown, | 369 |
PROPOSITION XX. | ||
The Absolute in Cognition, | 370 | |
Demonstration, | 370 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 371 | |
1. | Nothing is affirmed as to the existing Absolute, | 371 |
2. | Comment on definition of the known Absolute, | 371 |
3. | Twentieth Counter-proposition, | 372 |
4. | This counter-proposition is a reiteration of Counter-proposition XVI., | 372 |
PROPOSITION XXI. | ||
What the Absolute in Cognition is, | 373 | |
Demonstration, | 373 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 374 | |
1. | Comment on demonstration of Proposition XXI., | 374 |
2. | Twenty-first Counter-proposition, | 374 |
3. | Fruitlessness of the controversy respecting the Absolute and the Relative. The philosophical temper, | 375 |
4. | The causes of confusion in this controversy, | 377 |
5. | All men are equally cognisant of the absolute, | 378 |
6. | A reminder, | 379 |
7. | Confusion might have been obviated had it been shown that all men are equally cognisant of the absolute, | 379 |
8. | The difficulty is, not to know it, but to know that we know it, | 380 |
9. | Refutation of the relationist doctrine, | 380 |
10. | Kant on the Absolute, | 381 |
11. | The relation of non-contradictories and the relation of contradictories, | 383 |
PROPOSITION XXII. | ||
The Contingent Conditons of Knowledge, | 384 | |
Demonstration, | 384 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 385 | |
1. | This proposition takes us out of necessary into contingent truth, | 385 |
2. | It is introduced in order that the necessary may be separated from the contingent laws, | 386 |
3. | Why this analysis is indispensable, | 387 |
4. | What is required in setting about this analysis, | 388 |
5. | The analysis illustrated, | 388 |
6. | The analysis illustrated, | 390 |
7. | It is unnecessary to carry the analysis into greater detail, | 391 |
8. | How these remarks qualify the doctrine of the absolute given in Proposition XXI., | 392 |
9. | The absolute, however, is still object + subject. The main result of the epistemology, | 393 |
10. | Twenty-second Counter-proposition, | 393 |
11. | The chief point to be attended to in it, | 394 |
12. | The cause of the errors of representation ism pointed out., | 394 |
13. | The same subject continued, | 396 |
14. | The cause of Berkeley's errors pointed out, | 397 |
15. | The main result of the epistemology, | 399 |
16. | The importance of this result, | 401 |
SECTION II. | ||
THE AGNOIOLOGY, OR THEORY OF IGNORANCE. | ||
PROPOSITION I. | ||
What Ignorance is, | 405 | |
Demonstration, | 405 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 405 | |
1. | Why this proposition is introduced, | 405 |
2. | Novelty of the agnoiology, | 406 |
3. | The agnoiology is indispensable, | 406 |
4. | The plea of our ignorance a bar to ontology, | 407 |
5. | This obstacle can be removed only by an inquiry into the nature of ignorance, | 408 |
6. | First Counter-proposition, | 408 |
PROPOSITION II. | ||
Ignorance remediable, | 410 | |
Demonstration, | 410 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 410 | |
1. | All that this proposition proves, | 410 |
2. | Second Counter-proposition, | 411 |
PROPOSITION III. | ||
The Law of all Ignorance, | 412 | |
Demonstration, | 412 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 412 | |
1. | Importance of this proposition, | 413 |
2. | Symbols illustrative of the law of ignorance, | 413 |
3. | Distinction between ignorance and a nescience of the opposites of necessary truth, | 414 |
4. | There can be no ignorance of the opposites of the geometrical axioms., | 414 |
5. | There can be no ignorance of the contradictory, | 415 |
6. | Third Counter-proposition, | 416 |
PROPOSITION IV. | ||
Ignorance of Objects per se, | 417 | |
Demonstration, | 417 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 417 | |
1. | The truths now pour down fast, | 417 |
2. | Fourth Counter-proposition—is swept away, | 418 |
PROPOSITION V. | ||
Ignorance of Matter per se, | 419 | |
Demonstration, | 419 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 419 | |
1. | The main business of the agnoiology, | 420 |
2. | The disadvantage of not studying necessary truth, | 420 |
3. | The doctrine of ignorance entertained by psychology and common opinion, | 421 |
4. | The advantage of studying necessary truth, | 421 |
5. | The agnoiology carries out the work of the epistemology, | 422 |
6. | Fifth Counter-proposition, | 423 |
7. | Psychological conclusion as to our ignorance of matter per se, | 423 |
8. | It rests on a contradictory assumption, | 424 |
9. | The psychological conclusion, therefore, is contradictory, | 425 |
10. | The origin of the psychological mistake pointed out, | 425 |
11. | No ontology is possible if we can be ignorant of matter per se, | 426 |
PROPOSITION VI. | ||
Ignorance of the Universal and Particular, | 428 | |
Demonstration, | 428 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 428 | |
1. | Effect of this proposition, | 429 |
2. | Sixth Counter-proposition, | 429 |
3. | The error which it involves, | 429 |
PROPOSITION VII. | ||
Ignorance of the Ego per se, | 430 | |
Demonstration, | 430 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 430 | |
1. | Design and effect of this proposition, | 430 |
2. | Seventh Counter-proposition, | 431 |
3. | What the agnoiology does next, | 431 |
PROPOSITION VIII. | ||
The Object of All Ignorance, | 432 | |
Demonstration, | 432 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 433 | |
1. | Relation of this proposition to Proposition II. of the epistemology, | 433 |
2. | The object of ignorance is neither nothing nor the contradictory, | 434 |
3. | It is believed that this doctrine is new, | 435 |
4. | What has caused this doctrine to be missed, | 436 |
5. | Another circumstance which has caused it to be missed, | 437 |
6. | In fixing the object of ignorance this proposition does not deny its magnitude, | 438 |
7. | How far the object of ignorance is definable, and how far it is not definable, | 439 |
8. | The advantage of discriminating the necessary from the contingent laws of knowledge, | 440 |
9. | This system is more humble in its pretensions than other systems, | 442 |
10. | Eighth Counter-proposition, | 443 |
11. | The grounds on which it rests are false, | 443 |
12. | Illustration of the difference between the speculative and the ordinary view in regard to the object of ignorance, | 444 |
13. | The substantial and absolute in ignorance, | 446 |
14. | The main result of the agnoiology shortly stated, | 446 |
15. | Concluding remark, | 447 |
SECTION III. | ||
THE ONTOLOGY, OR THEORY OF BEING. | ||
PROPOSITION I. | ||
The Three Alternatives as to Absolute Existence, | 453 | |
Demonstration, | 453 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 454 | |
1. | The problem of ontology stated, | 454 |
2. | Its three alternatives are exhaustive, | 454 |
3. | The third alternative has to be eliminated, | 455 |
4. | First Counter-proposition, | 456 |
5. | In what respect this counter-proposition is right, | 456 |
6. | In what respect it is wrong, | 457 |
7. | The law of excluded middle stated, | 457 |
8. | How this law must be qualified, | 457 |
9. | Origin of the mistake in regard to this law, | 458 |
10. | The want of a clear doctrine of the contradictory has been the cause of much error in philosophy, | 459 |
11. | Distinction between the singly and the doubly contradictory., | 460 |
PROPOSITION II. | ||
A Premiss by which the Third Alternative is Eliminated, | 461 | |
Demonstration, | 461 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 462 | |
1. | Why this proposition is introduced, | 462 |
2. | Second Counter-proposition, | 462 |
3. | To what extent it is true, | 462 |
PROPOSITION III. | ||
A Premiss by which the Third Alternative is Eliminated, | 464 | |
Demonstration, | 464 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 464 | |
1. | The truth of this proposition is presupposed by the very nature of the inquiry, | 465 |
2. | Third Counter-proposition. Why there is none, | 466 |
PROPOSITION IV. | ||
Eliminates the Third Alternative, | 467 | |
Demonstration, | 467 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 467 | |
1. | What this proposition effects, | 467 |
2. | Fourth Counter-proposition. Why there is none, | 468 |
3. | The previous propositions are preliminary. Proposition V. is the starting-point, | 468 |
PROPOSITION V. | ||
The remaining Alternatives, | 469 | |
Demonstration, | 469 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 469 | |
1. | This proposition secures the key of the ontology, | 470 |
2. | Fifth Counter-proposition. Why there is none, | 471 |
PROPOSITION VI. | ||
What Absolute Existence is not, | 472 | |
Demonstration, | 472 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 473 | |
1. | Sixth Counter-proposition, | 473 |
2. | Is approved by ordinary thinking, and by psychology, | 473 |
3. | In what sense material things exist, | 473 |
PROPOSITION VII. | ||
What Absolute Existence is not, | 475 | |
Demonstration, | 475 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 476 | |
1. | Seventh Counter-proposition, | 476 |
PROPOSITION VIII. | ||
2. | Is approved by ordinary thinking, and by psychology, | 473 |
3. | In what sense material things exist, | 473 |
PROPOSITION VII. | ||
What Absolute Existence is not, | 475 | |
Demonstration, | 475 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 476 | |
1. | Seventh Counter-proposition, | 476 |
PROPOSITION VIII. | ||
What Absolute Existence is not, | 477 | |
Demonstration, | 477 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 477 | |
1. | Eighth Counter-proposition, | 478 |
2. | Importance of the ego as a constituent of Absolute Existence, | 478 |
3. | Why the reduction of the ego per se to a contradiction is important, | 478 |
PROPOSITION IX. | ||
The Origin of Knowledge, | 479 | |
Demonstration, | 479 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 479 | |
1. | Question as to the origin of knowledge—has been erroneously treated, | 480 |
2. | The assumption which vitiates the discussion, | 480 |
3. | First consequence of the assumption. Ninth Counter-proposition, | 481 |
4. | Second consequence. The doctrine of representationism, | 481 |
5. | The earliest form of representationism. Physical Influx, | 482 |
6. | Correction of this doctrine by Des Cartes, | 483 |
7. | Consequences of the Cartesian correction, | 484 |
8. | Scepticism and idealism arise, | 484 |
9. | The Cartesian salvo—hypothesis of "Occasional Causes." Its insufficiency, | 486 |
10. | Mallebranche: his "Vision of all things in God,", | 487 |
11. | Leibnitz: his "Pre-established Harmony,", | 488 |
12. | Character of these hypotheses, | 488 |
13. | Locke's explanation, | 489 |
14. | Berkeley: his doctrine of intuitive perception, | 490 |
15. | His fundamental defect, | 491 |
16. | Reid: his misunderstanding of Berkeley, | 492 |
17. | Reid failed to establish a doctrine of intuitive perception, | 493 |
18. | His character as a philosopher, | 494 |
19. | He mistook the vocation of philosophy, | 496 |
20. | Kant. "Innate Ideas,", | 497 |
21. | Right interpretation of this doctrine, | 497 |
22. | The circumstance to be particularly attended to in considering this doctrine, | 499 |
23. | The misconception to be particularly guarded against, | 499 |
24. | This misconception has never been guarded against by any philosopher, | 500 |
25. | Hence the ineptitude of the controversy, | 500 |
26. | In this controversy Kant is as much at fault as his predecessors, | 502 |
27. | How this system of Institutes avoids these errors, | 504 |
28. | First: it starts from no hypothesis, | 504 |
29. | Secondly: it finds that all cognition consists of two elements, | 505 |
30. | Thirdly: it finds that each element is no cognition, but only a half or part-cognition, | 505 |
31. | Fourthly: it finds that matter is only a half cognition, | 506 |
32. | Fifthly: it establishes "intuitive," and overthrows "representative" perception, | 506 |
33. | Sixthly: it steers clear of materialism, | 506 |
34. | Seventhly: it steers clear of spurious idealism, | 507 |
35. | Eighthly: it is under no obligation to explain the origin of knowledge, because knowledge itself is the Beginning, | 509 |
36. | The synthesis of ego and non-ego is original, and not factitious or secondary, | 510 |
PROPOSITION X. | ||
What Absolute Existence is, | 511 | |
Demonstration, | 511 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 512 | |
1. | This proposition solves the problem of ontology, | 512 |
2. | It answers the question; What is Truth?, | 513 |
3. | All Existence is the synthesis of the universal and the particular, | 514 |
4. | Thus the equation of the Known and the Existent has been proved, | 515 |
5. | The coincidence of the Absolute in Existence with the Absolute in Cognition has also been proved, | 516 |
6. | Attention called to restriction in foregoing paragraph, | 517 |
7. | Illustration of restriction—What the ontology gives out as alone Absolute Existence, | 517 |
8. | This paragraph qualifies a previous assertion, | 518 |
9. | In what sense we know, and in what sense we are ignorant of, Absolute Existence, | 519 |
10. | Tenth Counter-proposition, | 521 |
PROPOSITION XI. | ||
What Absolute Existence is Necessary, | 522 | |
Demonstration, | 522 | |
Observations and Explanations, | 523 | |
1. | Distinction taken in this proposition. Ontological proof of Deity, | 523 |
2. | The system is forced to this conclusion, | 525 |
3. | Eleventh Counter-proposition, | 525 |
Summary and Conclusion, | 526 | |
1. | The main question is—How has the system redeemed its pledges?, | 526 |
2. | It is submitted that the system is both reasoned and true, | 527 |
3. | The chief consideration to be looked to in estimating the system, | 527 |
4. | Its negative character is to be attended to principally, | 528 |
5. | The first step which the system takes in its negative or polemical character, | 528 |
6. | The next step which the system takes in its negative or polemical character, | 529 |
7. | The capital contradiction which the epistemology brings to light and corrects, | 529 |
8. | The second contradiction which it corrects, | 530 |
9. | The third contradiction which it corrects, | 531 |
10. | The fourth and fifth contradictions which it corrects, | 531 |
11. | The propositions and counter-propositions fall into groups, | 531 |
12. | The sixth contradiction which the epistemology corrects, | 532 |
13. | The seventh contradiction which it corrects, | 533 |
14. | The eighth contradiction which it corrects, | 533 |
15. | The ninth contradiction which it corrects, | 534 |
16. | The tenth contradiction which it corrects., | 534 |
17. | The eleventh, twelfth, and thirteenth contradictions which it corrects, | 535 |
18. | The remaining contradictions which it corrects., | 535 |
19. | The leading contradiction which the agnoiology corrects, | 536 |
20. | The derivative contradictions which it corrects, | 537 |
21. | The concluding contradiction which it corrects, | 537 |
22. | The opinions entertained by natural thinking, and to some extent by psychology, on the subject of "Being,", | 538 |
23. | How the ontology goes to work in exposing the contradictions involved in these opinions, | 538 |
24. | Exposure and refutation of these contradictions, | 539 |
25. | The ninth contradiction which the ontology corrects, | 539 |
26. | The tenth contradiction which the ontology corrects, | 540 |
27. | The eleventh contradiction which the ontology corrects, | 540 |
28. | By the correction of these contradictions, the system has redeemed its pledge, | 541 |
29. | The utility of philosophical study, | 541 |
30. | As a discipline of necessary and demonstrated truth, | 542 |
PAPERS SUPPLEMENTARY | ||
Letter to Mr De Quincy, | 547 | |
Appendix to 'Institutes of Metaphysic,' | 553 | |
Letter on some Objections to the 'Institutes,' | 582
|
This work was published before January 1, 1929, and is in the public domain worldwide because the author died at least 100 years ago.
Public domainPublic domainfalsefalse