Jump to content

The Spirit of Laws (1758)/Book XII

From Wikisource
The Spirit of Laws, Volume I (1758)
by Montesquieu, translated by Thomas Nugent
Book XII
Montesquieu2635064The Spirit of Laws, Volume I — Book XII1758Thomas Nugent


BOOK XII.
Of the Laws that form political Liberty as relative to the Subject.


CHAP. I.
Idea of this Book.

Book XII.
Chap. 1.
IT is not sufficient to have treated of political liberty as relative to the constitution; we must examine it likewise in the relation it bears to the subject.

We have observed that in the first case it is formed by a certain distribution of the three powers: but in the second we must consider it under another idea. It consists in security, or in the opinion people have of their security.

The constitution may happen to be free, and the subject not. The subject may be free, and not the constitution. In those cases, the constitution will be free by right and not in fact, the subject will be free in fact and not by right.

It is the disposition only of the laws, and even of the fundamental laws, that constitutes liberty in its relation to the constitution. But as it relates to the subject; morals, customs, or received examples may give rise to it, and particular civil laws may favour it, as we shall presently see in this book.

Farther, as in most states, liberty is more checked or depressed than their constitution demands, it is proper to treat of the particular laws Book XII.
Chap. 2.
that in each constitution are apt to assist or check the principle of liberty, which each state is capable of receiving.


CHAP. II.
Of the Liberty of the Subject.

PHilosophical liberty consists in the free exercise of the will; or at least, if we must speak agreeably to all systems, in an opinion that we have the free exercise of our will. Political liberty consists in security, or at least in the opinion th enjoy security.

This security is never more dangerously attacked than in public or private accusations. It is therefore on the goodness of criminal laws that the liberty of the subject principally depends.

Criminal laws did not receive their full perfection all at once. Even in places where liberty has been most fought after, it has not been always found. Aristotle[1] informs us that at Cumæ, the parents of the accuser might be witnesses. So imperfect was the law under the kings of Rome, that Servius Tullius pronounced sentence against the children of Ancus Martius, who were charged with having assassinated the king his father-in-law[2]. Under the first kings of France, Clotarius made a law[3], that no body should be condemned without being heard; which shews that a contrary custom had prevailed in some particular case or among some barbarous people. It was Charondas that first established penalties against false witnesses[4]. When the subject has no fence to secure his innocence, he has none for his liberty.

Book XII.
Chap. 3, & 4.
The knowledge already acquired in some countries, or that may be hereafter attained in others, in regard to the surest rules that can be observed in criminal judgments, is more interesting to mankind than any other thing in the universe.

Liberty can only be founded on the practice of this knowledge: and supposing a state to have the best laws imaginable in this respect, a person tried under that state, and condemned to be hanged the next day, would have much more liberty, than a bashaw enjoys in Turky.


CHAP. III.
The same Subject continued.

THOSE laws which condemn a man to death on the deposition of a single witness, are fatal to liberty. In right reason there should be two, because a witness who affirms, and the accused who denies, make an equal balance, and a third must incline the scale.

The Greeks[5] and Romans[6] required one voice more to condemn: but our French laws insist upon two. The Greeks pretend that their custom was established by the Gods[7]; but this more justly may be said of ours.


CHAP. IV.
That Liberty is favoured by the nature and proportion of Punishments.

LIBERTY is in its highest perfection, when criminal laws derive each punishment from the particular nature of the crime. There are then Book XII.
Chap. 4.
no arbitrary decisions; the punishment does not flow from the capriciousness of the legislator, but from the very nature of the thing; and man uses no violence to man.

There are four sorts of crimes. Those of the first species are prejudicial to religion, the second to morals, the third to the public tranquillity, and the fourth to the security of the subject. The punishments inflicted for these crimes ought to proceed from the nature of each of these species.

In the class of crimes that concern religion, I rank only those which attack it directly, such as all simple sacrileges. For as to crimes that disturb the exercise of it, they are of the nature of those which prejudice the tranquillity or security of the subject, and ought to be referred to those classes.

In order to derive the punishment of simple sacrileges from the nature of the thing[8], it should consist in depriving people of the advantages conferred by religion, in expelling them out of the temples, in a temporary or perpetual exclusion from the society of the faithful, in shunning their presence, in execrations, detestations, and conjurations.

In things that prejudice the tranquillity or security of the state, secret actions are subject to human jurisdiction. But in those which offend the Deity, where there is no public action, there can be no criminal matter; the whole passes betwixt man and God, who knows the measure and time of his vengeance. Now if magistrates, confounding things, should inquire also into hidden sacrileges, this Book XII.
Chap. 4.
inquisition would be directed to a kind of action that does not at all require it; the liberty of the subject would be subverted by arming the zeal of timorous, as well as of presumptuous conferences against him.

The mischief arises from a notion which some people have entertained of revenging the cause of the Deity. But we must honor the Deity, and leave him to avenge his own cause. In effect, were we to be directed by such a notion, where would be the end of punishments? If human laws are to avenge the cause of an infinite Being, they will be directed by his infinity, and not by the ignorance and caprice of man.

An historian[9] of Provence relates a fact, which furnishes us with an excellent description of the consequences that may arise in weak capacities from this notion of avenging the Deity's cause. A Jew was accused of having blasphemed against the blessed Virgin; and upon conviction, was condemned to be slead alive. A strange spectacle was then seen: gentlemen masked, with knives in their hands, ascended the scaffold, and drove away the executioner, in order to be the avengers themselves of the honor of the blessed Virgin.—I do not here chuse to anticipitate the reflections of the reader.

The second class consists of thole crimes which are prejudicial to morals. Such is the violation of public or private continency, that is, of the policy directing the manner in which the pleasure annexed to the union of bodies is to be enjoyed. The punishment of those crimes ought to be also derived from the nature of the thing; the privation of such advantages as society has attached to the purity of Book XII.
Chap. 4.
morals, fines, shame, necessity of concealment, public infamy, expulsion from home and society, and in fine all such punishments as belong to a corrective jurisdiction, are sufficient to repress the temerity of the two sexes. In effect, these things are less founded on malice, than on oblivion and self contempt.

We speak here of none but crimes that relate merely to morals, for as to those that are also prejudicial to the public security, such as rapes and ravishments, they belong to the fourth species.

The crimes of the third class are those that disturb the public tranquillity. The punishments ought therefore to be derived from the nature of the thing, and to be relative to this tranquillity; such as imprisonment, exile, corrections, and other-like chastisements, proper for reclaiming turbulent spirits, and reducing them to the established order.

I confine those crimes that injure the public tranquillity to things that imply a simple transgression against the civil administration: for as to those which by disturbing the public tranquillity attack at the same time the security of the subject, they ought to be ranked in the fourth class.

The punishments inflicted upon the latter crimes are such as are properly distinguished by that name. They are a kind of retaliation, by which the society refuses security to a member, who has actually or intentionally deprived another of his security. These punishments are derived from the nature of the thing, founded on reason, and drawn from the very source of good and evil. A man deserves death when he has violated the secunty so far as to deprive, or to attempt to deprive another man of his like. This punishment of death is the remedy, as it Book XII.
Chap. 4, & 5.
were, of a sick society. When there is a breach of security in respect to property, there may be some reasons for inflicting a capital punishment: but it would be much better, and perhaps more natural, that crimes committed against the security of property should be punished with the loss of property; and this ought indeed to be the case if mens fortunes were common or equal. But as those who have no property are generally the readiest to attack the property of others, it has been found necessary, instead of a pecuniary, to substitute a corporal punishment.

All that I have here advanced, is founded in nature, and extremely favourable to the liberty of the subject.


CHAP. V.
Of certain Accusations that require particular Moderation and Prudence.

IT is an important maxim; that we ought to be very circumspect in the prosecution of magic and heresy. The accusation of these two crimes may be vastly injurious to liberty, and productive of an infinite number of oppressions, if the legislator knows not how to set bounds to it. For as it does not aim directly at a person's actions, but at his character, it grows dangerous in proportion to the ignorance of the people; and then a man is always in danger, because the most unexceptionable conduct, the purest morals, and the constant practice of every duty in life, are not a sufficient security against the suspicion of his being guilty of crimes like these.

Book XII.
Chap. 5.
Under Manuel Comnenus, the Protestator[10] was accused of having conspired against the emperor, and of having employed for that purpose some secrets that render men invisible. It is mentioned in the life or this emperor[11] that Aaron was detected, as he was poring over a book of Solomon's, the reading of which was sufficient to conjure up whole legions of devils. Now by supposing a power in magic to arm all hell, people look upon a man whom they call a magician as the fittest person in the world to trouble and subvert society, and of course they are disposed to punish him with the utmost severity.

But their indignation increases when magic is supposed to have a power of subverting religion. The history of Constantinople[12] informs us, that in consequence of a revelation made to a bishop of a miracle's having ceased because of the magic practices of a certain person, both that person and his son were put to death. On how many surprizing things did not this single crime depend? That revelations should not be uncommon, that the bishop should be favoured with one, that it was real, that there had been a miracle in the case, that this miracle had ceased, that there was an art magic, that magic could subvert religion, that this particular person was a magician, and in fine, that he had committed that action of magic.

The emperor Theodorus Lascaris attributed his illness to magic. Those who were accused of this crime, had no other resource left than to handle a hot iron without being hurt. Thus among the Greeks a person ought to have been a magician to be able to clear himself of the imputation of magic. Book XII.
Chap. 6.
Such was the excess of their stupidity, that to the most dubious crime in the world, they joined the most dubious proofs of innocence.

Under the reign of Philip the Long, the Jews were expelled from France, being accused of having poisoned the springs with their lepers. So absurd an accusation ought very well to make us doubt of all those that are founded on public hatred.

I have not here asserted that heresy ought not to be punished; I said only that we ought to be extremely circumspect in punishing it.


CHAP. VI.
Of the Crime against Nature.

GOD forbid that I should have the least inclination to diminish the horror people have for a crime which religion, morality, and civil government equally condemn. It ought to be proscribed were it only for its communicating to one sex the weaknesses of the other, and for leading people by a scandalous prostitution of their youth, to an ignominious old age. What I shall say concerning it will no ways diminish its infamy, being levelled only against the tyranny that may abuse the very horror we ought to have for the vice.

As the nature of this crime is secrecy, there are frequent instances of its having been punished by legislators upon the deposition of a child. This was opening a very wide door to calumny. "Justinian, says Procopius[13], published a law against this crime; be ordained an enquiry to be made not only against those who were guilty of it, after the enacting of that law, but even before. The Book XII.
Chap. 6.
deposition of a single witness, sometimes of a child, sometimes of a slave, was sufficient, especially against such as were rich, and against those that were of the green faction."

It is very odd that these three crimes, magic, heresy, and that against nature, of which the first might easily be proved not to exist at all; the second to be susceptible of an infinite number of distinctions, interpretations, and limitations; the third to be often obscure and uncertain; it is very odd, I say, that these three crimes should amongst us be punished with fire.

I may venture to affirm that the crime against nature will never make any great progress in society, unless people find themselves induced to it in other respects by some particular custom; as among the Greeks where the young people performed all their exercises naked; as amongst us where domestic education is disused; as among the Asiatics where particular persons have a great number of women whom they despise, while others can have none at all. Let there be no customs preparatory to this crime, let it, like every other violation of morals, be severely proscribed by the civil magistrate, and nature will soon be seen to defend or resume her rights. Nature, that tender, amiable, and loving parent, has strewed her pleasures with a bounteous hand, and while she fills us with delights, she prepares us for future satisfactions of a more exquisite kind than those delights themselves.


CHAP. VII.
Of the Crime of high Treason.

Book XII.
Chap. 7, & 8.
IT is determined by the laws of China, that whosoever shews any disrespect to the emperor, is to be punished with death. As they do not mention in what this disrespect consists, every thing may furnish a pretext to take away a man's life, and to exterminate any family whatsoever.

Two persons of that country, who were employed to the court gazette, having inserted some circumstances relating to a certain fact, that were not true; it was pretended that to tell a lye in the court gazette, was a disrespect shewn to the court, in consequence of which they were put to death[14]. A prince of the blood having inadvertently made some mark on a memorial signed with the red pencil by the emperor, it was determined that he had behaved disrespectfully to that prince; which was the cause of one of the most terrible persecutions against that family that ever was recorded in history[15].

If the crime of high treason be indeterminate, this alone is sufficient to make the government degenerate into arbitrary power. I shall descant more largely on this subject, when I come to treat[16] of the composition of laws.


CHAP. VIII.
Of the bad Application of the Name of Sacrilege and high Treason.

IT is likewise a shocking abuse to give the appellation of high treason to an action that does Book XII.
Chap. 8.
not deserve it. It was decreed by an imperial law[17], that those who called in question the prince's judgment, or doubted of the merit of such as he had chosen tor a public office, should be prosecuted as guilty of sacrilege[18], Surely it was the cabinet council and the favourites of the court who invented that crime. By another law it was determined, that whosoever made any attempt against the ministers and officers of the prince should be deemed guilty of high treason, as if he had attempted against the prince himself[19]. This law is owing to two princes[20], celebrated in history for their weakness; princes who were led by their ministers as flocks by shepherds; princes who were slaves in the palace, children in the council, strangers to the army; princes in fine, who preserved their authority only by giving it away every day. Some of those favourites conspired against their emperors. Nay, they did more, they conspired against the empire; they called in barbarous nations; and when the emperors wanted to stop their progress, the state was so enfeebled, as to be under a necessity of infringing their law, and of exposing itself to the crime of high treason in order to punish those favourites.

And yet this is the very law which the judge of Monsieur de Cinq-Mars built upon[21], when endeavouring to prove that the latter was guilty of the crime of high treason for attempting to remove Cardinal Richelieu from the ministry, he says, "Crimes that aim at the persons of ministers, are Book XII.
Chap. 8, & 9.
deemed by the Imperial constitutions, of equal consequence with those which are levelled against the emperor's own person. A minister discharges his duty to his prince and to his country; to attempt therefore to remove him, is endeavouring to deprive the former of one of his arm[22], and the latter of part of its power." If even slavery herself was to defend upon the earth, she could not speak in any other language.

By another law of Valentinian, Theodosius, and Arcadius[23], false coiners are declared guilty of high treason. But is not this confounding the ideas of things? Is not the very horror of high treason diminished, by giving that name to another crime?


CHAP. IX.
The same Subject continued.

PAULINUS having wrote to the emperor Alexander, that "he was preparing to prosecute for high treason, a judge who had decided contrary to his edict." The emperor answered, "that under his reign there was no such thing as indirect high treason[24]."

Faustinian wrote to the same emperor, that as he had sworn by the prince's life never to pardon his slave, he found himself thereby obliged to perpetuate his wrath lest he should incur the guilt of high treason. Upon which the emperor made answer, "Your fears are groundless[25], and you are a stranger to my principles."

Book XII.
Chap. 9, & 10.
It was determined by a senatus-consultum[26], that whosoever melted down any of the emperor's statues which should happen to be rejected, should not be deemed guilty of high treason. The emperors Severus and Antoninus wrote to Pontius[27]; that those who sold unconsecrated statues of the emperor, should not be charged with high treason. The same princes wrote to Julius Cassianus, that if any person when slinging a stone should by chance strike one of the emperor's statues, he should not be liable to a prosecution of high treason[28]. The Julian law requires this sort of limitations; for in virtue of this law the crime of high treason was charged not only upon those who melted down the emperor's statues, but likewise on those who committed any such like action[29], which made it an arbitrary crime. When a number of crimes of high treason had been established, they were obliged to distinguish the several sorts. Hence Ulpian the civilian, after saying that the accusation of high treason did not die with the criminal, he adds, that this does not relate to[30] all the treasonable acts established by the Julian law, but only to that which implies an attempt against the empire or against the emperor's life.


CHAP. X.
The same Subject continued.

THERE was a law passed in England under Henry VIII. by which whosoever predicted the king's death, was declared guilty of high treason. This law was very indeterminate; the terror of despotic power is so great, that it even turns against those who exercise it. In this king's Book XII.
Chap. 11, & 12.
last illness, the physicians would not venture to say he was in danger; and surely they acted very right[31].


CHAP. XI.
Of Thoughts.

MARSYAS dreamt that he had cut Dionysius's throat[32]. Dionysius put him to death, pretending that he would never have dreamt of such a thing by night, if he had not thought of it by day. This was a most tyrannical action; for though it had been the subject of his thoughts, yet he had made no attempt[33] towards it. The laws do not take upon them to punish any other than overt acts.


CHAP. XII.
Of indiscreet Speeches.

NOTHING renders the crime of high treason more arbitrary than declaring people guilty of it for indiscreet speeches. Speech is so subject to interpretation; there is so great a difference between indiscretion and malice, and frequently so little is there of the latter in the expressions used, that the law can hardly subject people to a capital punishment for words, unless it expressly declares what words they are which render a man guilty[34].

Book XII.
Chap. 12.
Words do not constitute an overt act; they remain only in idea. They generally, when considered by themselves, have no determinate signification; for this depends on the tone in which they are uttered. It often happens that in repeating the same words, they have not the same meaning; this meaning depends on their connection with other things; and sometimes more is expressed by silence than by any discourse whatsoever. As there can be nothing so equivocal and ambiguous as all this; how is it possible to convert it into a crime of high treason? Where-ever this law is established; there is an end not only of liberty, but even of its very shadow.

In the manifesto of the late Czarina against the family of the D'Olgorucky's[35], one of these princes is condemned to death for having uttered some indecent words concerning her person; another for having maliciously interpreted her sage regulations for the welfare of the empire, and for having offended her sacred person by disrespectful words.

Not that I pretend to diminish the indignation people ought to have against those who presume to stain the glory of their prince; what I mean is, that if despotic princes are willing to moderate their power, a simple correction would be more proper on those occasions, than an accusation of high treason, a thing always terrible even to innocence itself[36].

Overt acts are not things that happen every days; they are liable to the observation of a great many people; and a false charge in respect to facts may Book XII.
Chap. 12, & 13.
be easily detected. Words joined to an action assume the nature of this action. Thus a man who goes into a public market place to incite the subjects to revolt, incurs the guilt of high treason, because the words are joined to the action, and partake of its nature. It is not the words that are punished, but an action in which words are employed. They do not become criminal, but when they prepare for, accompany, or follow a criminal action: every thing is confounded, if words are construed as a capital crime instead of considering them only as a mark of a capital crime.

The emperors Theodosius, Arcadius, and Honorius wrote thus to Rufinus who was præfectus prætorio. "If a man speaks amiss of our person, or government, we do not for all that intend to punish him[37]; if he has spoke through levity, we must despise him; if through folly, we must pity him; and if he wrongs us, we mujst forgive him. Wherefore leaving things as they are, you must inform us accordingly, that we way be able to judge of words by persons, and that we may well consider whether we ought to punish or overlook them."


CHAP. XIII.
Of Writings.

IN writings there is something more permanent than in words; but when they are no way preparative to high treason, they are not a subject of that crime.

Book XII.
Chap. 13.
And yet Augustus and Tiberius subjected satyrical writers to the same punishment as for having violated the law of majesty. Augustus[38], because of those which he suspected to have been written against himself. Nothing was more fatal to Roman liberty. Cremutius Cordus was accused for having called Cassius in his annals the last of the Romans[39].

Satyncal writings are hardly known in despotic governments, where dejection of mind on the one hand, and ignorance on the other, afford neither abilities nor will to write. In democracies they are not hindered for the very same reason, which causes them to be prohibited in monarchies: Being generally levelled against men of power and authority, they flatter the malignity of the people who are the governing party. In monarchies they are forbidden, but rather as a subject of civil animadversion, than as a capital crime. They may amuse the general malignity, please the malecontents, diminish the envy against public employments, give the people patience to suffer, and make them laugh at their sufferings.

But no government is so averse to fatyrical writings as the aristocratical. There the magistrates are petty sovereigns, but not great enough to despise affronts. If in a monarchy a fatyrical stroke is designed against the prince, he is placed in such an eminence that it does not reach him; but an aristocratical lord is pierced to the very heart. Hence the decemvirs who formed an aristocracy, punished fatyrical writings with death[40].


CHAP. XIV.
Breach of Modesty in punishing Crimes.

Book XII.
Chap. 14, & 15.
THERE are rules of modesty observed by almost every nation in the world; now it would be very absurd to infringe these rules in the punishment of crimes, the principal view or which ought always to be the establishment of order.

Was it the intent of those oriental nations who exposed women to elephants trained up for an abominable kind of punishment, was it, I say, their intent to establish one law by the breach of another?

By an ancient custom of the Romans it was not permitted to put girls to death till they were ripe for marriage. Tiberius found out an expedient of having them debauched by the executioner before they were brought to the place of punishment[41]: thus this bloody and subtle tyrant destroyed the morals or the people to preserve their customs.

When the magistrates of Japan caused women to be exposed naked in the market-places, and obliged them to go upon all four like beasts, modesty was shocked[42]: but when they wanted to compel a mother—when they wanted to force a son—I cannot proceed; even nature herself was struck with horror.


CHAP. XV.
Of the Infranchisement of Slaves in order to accuse their Master.

AUGUSTUS made a law that the slaves of those who conspired against his person, Book XII.
Chap. 15, & 16.
should be sold to the public that they might depose against their master[43]. Nothing ought to be neglected that may contribute to the discovery of an heinous crime; it is natural therefore that in a government where there are slaves they should be allowed to inform; but they ought not to be admitted as witnesses.

Vindex discovered the conspiracy that had been formed in favour of Tarquin; but he was not admitted a witness against the children of Brutus. It was right to give liberty to a person who had rendered so great a service to his country; but it was not given him in order to enable him to render this service.

Hence the emperor Tacitus ordained that slaves should not be admitted as witnesses against their masters, even in the case of high treason[44]: a law which was not inserted in Justinian's complement.


CHAP. XVI.
Of Calumny in respect to the Crime of high Treason.

TO do justice to the Cæsars, they were not the first devisers of the dismal laws which they enacted. It is Sylla[45] that taught them that calumniators ought not to be punished; but the thing was soon carried so far as to reward them[46].


CHAP. XVII.
Of the revealing of Conspiracies.

Book XII.
Chap. 17.
IF thy brother the son of thy mother, or thy son, or thy daughter, or the wife of thy bosom, or thy friend, which is as thine own soul, entire thee secretly, saying, Let us go and serve other gods, thou shalt surely kill him, thou shalt stone him[47]. This law of Deuteronomy cannot be a civil law among most of the nations known to us, because it would pave the way for all manner of wickedness.

No less severe is the law of several countries, which commands the subjects, on pain of death, to disclose conspiracies in which they are not even so much as concerned. When such a law is established in a monarchical government, it is very proper it should be under some restrictions.

It ought not to be applied in its full severity, but to the strongest cases of high treason. In those countries it is of the utmost importance not to confound the different degrees of this crime. In Japan, where the laws subvert every idea of human reason, the crime of concealment is applied even to the most ordinary cases.

A certain relation[48] makes mention of two young ladies, who were shut up for life in a box thick set with pointed nails, one for having had a love intrigue, and the other for not disclosing it.


CHAP. XVIII.
How dangerous it is in Republics to be too severs in punishing the Crime of high Treason.

Book XII.
Chap. 18.
AS soon as a republic has compassed the destruction of those who wanted to subvert it, there should be an end of examples, punishments, and even of rewards.

Great punishments,and consequently great changes, cannon take place without investing some citizens with too great a power. It is therefore more adviseable in this case to exceed in lenity, than in severity; to banish but few, rather than many; and to leave them their estates, rather than to make a great number of confiscations. Under pretence of avenging the republic's cause, the avengers would establish tyranny. The business is not to destroy the rebel but the rebellion. They ought to return as quick as possible into the usual track of government, in which every one is protected by the laws, and no one injured.

We find in Appian[49], the edict and formula of the proscriptions. One would imagine that they had no other aim than the good or the republic, so cooly they speak, so many advantages they point out, so preferable are the means they take to others, such security they promise to the rich, such tranquillity to the poor, so afraid they seem to be of endangering the lives of the subjects, so desirous of appealing the soldiers: a dreadful example, which shews how near severe punishments border upon tyranny.

Book XII.
Chap. 18, & 19.
The Greeks set no bounds to the vengeance they took of tyrants or of those they suspected of tyranny; they put their children to death[50], nay sometimes five of their nearest relations[51]; and they proscribed an infinite number of families. By this mans their republics suffered the most violent shooks; exiles or the return of the exiled were always epochas that indicated a change of the constitution.

The Romans had more sense. When Cassius was put to death for having aimed at tyranny, the question was proposed whether his children should undergo the same tare: but they were preserved. "They, says Dionysius Halicarnasseus[52]: who wanted to change this law at the end of the Marsian and civil wars, and to exclude from public offices the children of those who had been proscribed by Sylla, are very much to blame."


CHAP. XIX.
In what manner the Use of Liberty is suspended in a Republic.

IN countries where liberty is most esteemed, there are laws by which a single person is deprived of it, in order to preserve it for the whole community. Such are in England what they call Bills of Attainder[53]. These are relative to those Athenian Book XII.
Chap. 19, & 20.
laws by which a private person was condemned[54], provided they were made by the unanimous suffrage of six thousand citizens. They are relative also to those laws which were made at Rome against private citizens, and were called privileges[55]. These were never passed but in the great meetings of the people. But in what manner soever they are enacted, Cicero is for having them abolished, because the force of law consists in its being made for the whole community[56]. I must own, notwithstanding, that the practice of the freest nation that ever existed, induces me to think that there are cases in which a veil should be drawn for a while over liberty, as it was customary to veil the statues of the Gods.


CHAP. XX.
Of Laws favourable to the Liberty of the Subject in a Republic.

IN popular governments it often happens that accusations are carried on in public, and every man is allowed to accuse whomsoever he pleases. This rendered it necessary to establish proper laws in order to protect the innocence of the subject. At Athens if an accuser had not the fifth part of the votes on his side, he was obliged to pay a fine of a thousand drachms. Æschines who accused Ctesiphon, was condemned to pay this fine[57]. At Rome a false accuser was branded with infamy[58], by marking the letter K on his forehead. Guards Book XII.
Chap. 21.
were also appointed to watch the accuser, in order to prevent his corrupting either the judges or the witnesses[59].

I have already taken notice of that Athenian and Roman law, by which the party accused was allowed to withdraw before judgment was pronounced.


CHAP. XXI.
Of the Cruelty of Laws in respect to debtors in a Republic.

GREAT is the superiority which one fellow-subject has already over another, by lending him money, which the latter borrows in order to spend, and of course has no longer in his possession. What must be the consequence if the laws of a republic make a farther addition to this servitude and subjection?

At Athens and Rome[60] it was at first permitted to sell such debtors as were insolvent. Solon redressed this abuse at Athens[61]; by ordaining that no man's body should answer for his civil debts. But the decemvirs[62] did not reform the same custom at Rome; and though they had Solon's regulation before their eyes, yet they did not chuse to follow it. This is not the only passage of the law of the twelve tables, in which the decemvirs shew their design of checking the spirit of democracy.

Often did those cruel laws against debtors throw the Roman republic into danger. A man all covered Book XII.
Chap. 22.
with wounds, made his escape from his creditor's house, and appeared in the forum[63]. The people were moved with this spectacle, and other citizens whom their creditors durst no longer confine, emerged from their dungeons. They had promises made them, which were all broke. The people upon this having withdrawn to the Sacred Mount, obtained, not an abrogation of those laws, but a magistrate to defend them. Thus they quitted a slate of anarchy, but were soon in danger of falling into tyranny. Manlius to render himself popular, was going to set those citizens at liberty, who had been reduced to slavery by their inhuman creditors[64]. Manlius's designs were prevented, but without remedying the evil. Particular laws facilitated to debtors the means of paying[65], and in the year of Rome 428 the consuls proposed a law[66] which deprived creditors of the power of confining their debtors in their own houses[67]. An usurer, by name Papirius attempted to corrupt the chastity of a young man named Publius, whom he kept in irons. Sextus's crime gave to Rome its political liberty; that of Papirius gave it also the civil.

Such was the fate of this city, that new crimes confirmed the liberty, which those of a more ancient date had procured it. Appius's attempt upon Virginia, flung the people again into that horror against tyrants with which the misfortune of Lucretia had first inspired them. Thirty seven years after[68] the crime of the infamous Papirius, an action of the Book XII.
Chap, 22.
like criminal nature[69] was the cause of the people's retiring to the Janiculum[70], and of giving new vigor to the law made for the safety of debtors.

Since that time creditors were oftener prosecuted by debtors for having violated the laws against usury, than the latter were sued for refilling to pay them.


CHAP. XXII.
Of things that strike at Liberty in Monarchies.

LIBERTY has been often weakened in monarchies by a thing of the least use in the world to the prince: this is the naming of commissioners to try a private person.

The prince himself derives so very little advantage from those commissioners, that it is not worth while to change tor their sake the common course of things. He is morally sure that he has more of the spirit of probity and justice than his commissioners, who always think themselves sufficiently justified by his orders, by a dubious interest of state, by the choice that has been made of them, and even by their very apprehensions.

Upon the arraigning of a peer under Henry VIII. it was customary to try him by a committee of the house of lords: by this means he put to death as many peers as he pleased.


CHAP. XXIII.
Of Spies in Monarchies.

Book XII.
Chap. 23.
SHOULD I be asked whether there is any necessity for spies in monarchies; my answer would be, that the usual practice of good princes is not to employ them. When a man obeys the laws, he has discharged his duty to his prince. He ought at least to have his own house for an asylum, and the rest of his conduct should be exempt from inquiry. The spying-trade might perhaps be tolerable, were it practised by honest men; but the necessary infamy of the person is sufficient to make us judge of the infamy of the thing. A prince ought to act towards his subjects with candor, frankness, and confidence. He that has so much disquiet, suspicion and fear, is an actor embarrassed in playing his part. When he finds that the laws are generally observed and reflected, he may judge himself safe. The general behaviour of the public answers for that of every individual. Let him not be afraid: he cannot imagine how natural it is for his people to love him. And how should they do otherwise than love him? since he is the source of almost all the favours that are shewn; punishments being generally charged to the account of the laws. He never shews himself to his people but with a serene countenance; they have even a share of his glory, and they are protected by his power. A proof of his being beloved is that his subjects have a confidence in him; what the minister refuses, they imagine the prince would have granted: even under public calamities they do not accuse his Book XII.
Chap. 24.
person; they are apt to complain of his being misinformed, or beset by corrupt men: Did the prince but know, say the people; these words are a kind of invocation and a proof of the confidence they have in his person.


CHAP. XXIV.
Of Anonymous Letters.

THE Tartars are obliged to put their names to their arrows, that the arm may be known that shoots them. When Philip of Macedon was wounded at the siege of a certain town, these words were found on the javelin, After has given this mortal wound to Philip[71]. If they who accuse a person did it merely to serve the public, they would not carry their complaint to the prince, who may be easily prejudiced, but to the magistrates who have rules that are formidable only to calumniators. But if they are unwilling to leave the laws open between them and the accused, it is a presumption they have reason to be afraid of them; and the least punishment they ought to suffer, is not to be credited. No notice therefore should ever be taken of those letters but in cases that cannot admit of the delays of the ordinary course ot justice, and where the prince's welfare is concerned. Then it may be imagined that the accuser has made an effort which has untied his tongue and made him speak. But in other cases one ought to say with the emperor Constantius: "We cannot suspect a person who has wanted an accuser, whilst he did not want an enemy[72]."


CHAP. XXV.
Of the manner of governing in Monarchies.

Book XII.
Chap. 25, & 26.
THE royal authority is a great spring that ought to move easily and without noise. The Chinese boast of one of their emperors, who governed, they say, like the heavens, that is, by his example.

There are some cases in which a sovereign ought to exert the full extent of his power; and others in which he ought to reduce it within its proper limits. The sublimity of administration consists in knowing perfectly the proper degree of power, that should be exerted on different occasions.

The whole felicity of our monarchies consists in the opinion people have of the lenity of the government. A wrong-headed minister always wants to remind us of our slavery. But granting even that we are slaves, he ought to endeavour to conceal our miserable condition from us. All he can say or write, is that the prince is uneasy, that he is surprised, and that he will set things to rights. There is a certain ease in commanding; the prince ought only to encourage, and leave the menacing part to the laws[73].


CHAP. XXVI.
That in a Monarchy the Prince ought to be of easy Access.

THE utility of this maxim will appear better from the inconveniency attending the Book XII.
Chap. 29.
contrary practice. "The Czar Peter I. says the Sieur Perry[74], has to published a new edict, by which he forbids any of his subjefts to offer him a petition till after having presented it to two of his officers. In case of a refusal of justice they may present him a third, but upon pain of death if they are in the wrong. After this no one ever presumed to offer a petition to the Czar."


CHAP. XXVII.
Of the Manners of a Monarch.

THE manners of a prince contribute as much as the laws themselves to liberty; like these he may transform men into beasts, and beasts into men. It he likes free and noble souls, he will have subjects; if he likes base and dastardly spirits, he will have slaves. Does he want to know the great art of ruling? Let him call honor and virtue around his person, let him invite personal merit. He may even sometimes cast an eye on talents and abilities. Let him not be afraid of those rivals who are called men of merit; he is their equal as soon as he loves them. Let him gain the hearts of his people without bringing their spirits into subjection. Let him render himself popular; he ought to be pleased with the affection of the lowest of his subjects, for they too are men. The common people require so very little deference, that it is fit they should be humoured; the infinite distance between the sovereign and them will surely prevent them from giving him any uneasiness. Let him be exorable to supplication, and resolute against demands; let him be Book XII.
Chap, 28.
sensible, in fine, that his people have his refusals, while his courtiers enjoy his favours.


CHAP. XXVIII.
Of the Regard which Monarchs owe to their Subjects.

PRINCES ought to be extremely circumspect in point of raillery. It pleases with moderation, because it opens the way to familiarity; but a biting raillery is less excusable in them than in the meanest of their subjects, for it is they alone that give a mortal wound.

Much less ought they to offer a notorious insult to any of their subjects; kings were instituted to pardon, and to punish, but never to insult.

When they insult their subjects, their treatment is more cruel than that of the Turk or the Muscovite. The insults of the latter are a humiliation, not a disgrace , but both must follow from the insults of the former.

Such is the prejudice of the eastern nations, that they look upon an affront coming from the prince, as the effect of paternal goodness; and such on the contrary is our way of thinking, that to the cruel vexation of being affronted, we join the despair of ever being able to wipe off the disgrace.

Princes ought to be overjoyed to have subjects to whom honor is dearer than life, an incitement to fidelity as well as to courage.

They should remember the misfortunes that have happened to princes for insulting their subjects, the revenge of Chærea, of the eunuch Narses, of count Julian, and in fine of the dutchess of Montpensier, who being enraged against Henry III. for having Book XII.
Chap. 29.
published some of her private failings, plagued him all his life.


CHAP. XXIX.
Of the civil Laws proper for mixing a little Liberty in a despotic Government.

THOUGH despotic governments are of their own nature every where the same; yet from circumstances, from an opinion of religion, from prejudice, from received examples, from a particular turn of mind, from manners or morals, it is possible they may admit of a considerable difference.

It is useful that some particular notions should be established in those governments, thus in China the prince is considered as the father of his people; and at the commencement of the empire of the Arabs, the prince was their preacher[75].

It is proper there should be some sacred book to serve for a rule, as the Koran among the Arabs, the books of Zoroaster among the Persians, the Vedam among the Indians, and the classic Books among the Chinese. The religious code supplies the civil one, and directs the arbitrary power.

It is not at all amiss that in dubious cases the judges should consult the ministers of religion[76]. Thus in Turky the Cadis consult the Mollachs. But if it is a capital crime, it may be proper for the particular judge, if such there be, to take the governor's advice, to the end that the civil and ecclesiastic power may be tempered also by the political authority.


CHAP. XXX.
The same Subject continued.

Book XII.
Chap. 30.
NOTHING but the very excess and fury of despotic power ordained that the father's disgrace should drag after it that of his wife and children. They are wretched enough already without being criminals: besides, the prince ought to leave suppliants or mediators between himself and the accused, to asswage his wrath, or to inform his justice.

It is an excellent custom of the Maldivians[77], that when a lord is disgraced, he goes every day to pay his court to the king till he is taken again into favour: his presence disarms the prince's wrath.

In some despotic governments[78] they have a notion that it is trespassing against the respect due to their prince, to speak to him in favour of a person in disgrace. These princes seem to use all their endeavours to deprive themselves of the virtue of clemency.

Arcadius and Honorius, in a law[79] which we have already descanted upon[80], positively declare that they will shew no favor to those who shall presume to petition them in behalf of the guilty[81]. This was a very bad law indeed, since it is bad even under a despotic government.

The custom or Persia, which permits every man that pleases, to leave the kingdom, is excellent; Book XII.
Chap. 30.
and though the contrary practice derives its origin from despotic power, which has always looked upon subjects as slaves[82], and those who quit the country as fugitives, yet the Persian practice is useful even to a despotic government, because the apprehension of the flight, or of the withdrawing of debtors, puts a stop to, or moderates the oppressions of bashaws and extortioners.

  1. Politics book 2.
  2. Tarquinius Priseus. See Dionysius Halicarn. book 4.
  3. As early as the year 560.
  4. Aristot. Polit. book 2. chap. 12. He gave his laws at Thurium in the 84th Olympiad.
  5. See Aristid. Orat. in Mineryam.
  6. Dionys. Halicarn. on the judgment of Coriolanu, book 7.
  7. Minervæ calculus.
  8. St. Lewis made such severe laws against those who swore, that the pope thought himself obliged to admonish him for it. This prince moderated his zeal, and softened his laws(s***???).
  9. Farther Bougerel.
  10. Micetas, life of Manuel Comnenus, Book 4.
  11. Ibid.
  12. History of the emperor Maurice by Theophylactus, Chap. 11.
  13. Secret History.
  14. Father Du Halde, Tom 1. p. 43.
  15. Father Parennin in the edifying letters.
  16. Book 29.
  17. Gratian, Valentinian, and Theodosius. This is the second in the Code de Crimin. Sacril.
  18. Sacrilegii instar est dubitare an is dignus sit quem elegerit Imperator. ibid. This law served as a model to that of Roger in the constitutions of Naples, Tit. 4.
  19. THe 5th law ad leg. Jul. Maj.
  20. Arcadius & Honorius.
  21. Memoirs of Montrefor Tom. 1.
  22. Nam ipsi pars corporis nostri sunt The same law of the Code ad Maj. leg. Jul.
  23. It is the 9th of the Code Theodos de falsa monta.
  24. Etiam ex aliis causis majestatis crimina cessant meo sæculo. Leg. 1. eod. ad leg. Jul. Maj.
  25. Alienam sectæ meæsfollicitudinem concepisti. Leg. 2. eod. ad leg. Jul. Maj.
  26. See the 4th law in ff. ad leg.. Jul. Maj.
  27. See the 5th law, ibid.
  28. Ibid.
  29. Aliudve quid simile admiserint. ad leg. Jul. Maj.
  30. In the last law in ff. ad leg. Jul. de Adulteriis.
  31. See Burnet's History of the Reformation.
  32. Plutarch, life of Dionysius.
  33. The thought must be joined with some sort of action.
  34. Si non tale sit delictum in quod vel sciptura legis descendit vel ad exemplum legis vindicandum est, says Modestinus in the seventh law, in ff, ad leg. Jul. Maj.
  35. In 1740.
  36. Nec lubricum linguæ ad pænam sacile trabendum est. Modestin. in the 7th law in ff. ad leg. Jul. Maj.
  37. Si id ex legitate pracesserit, contemnendum est; si ex insania, miseratione dignissimum; isi ab injuria, renittendum, Leg. unica Cod. St quis Imperat, maled.
  38. Tacitus's Annals, Book 1. This continued under the following Reigns. See the first law in the Code de famosis libellis.
  39. Tacit. Annal. Book 4.
  40. The law of the twelve tables.
  41. Suetenius in Tiberis.
  42. Collection of voyages that contributed to the establishment of the East India company. Tom 5. Part 2.
  43. Dio in Xiphilinus.
  44. Flavius Vopiscus in his life.
  45. Sylla made a law of Majesty, which is mentioned in Cicero's orations, pro Cluentio, Art. 3. in Pisonem, Art. 21. 2d. against Verres, Art. 5. familiar epistles, Book 3. Letter 11. Cæsar and Augustus inserted them in the Julian laws; others made additions to them.
  46. Et quò quis distinctior accusator eò magis honores assequebatur, ac veluti sacrosanctus erat. Tacit.
  47. Deuteron. chap. xiii. 6.
  48. Collection of voyages that contributed to the establishment of the East India company Book 5. Part 2. p. 423.
  49. Of the civil wars, Book 4.
  50. Dionys. Halicarn. Roman Antiquitiers, book 8.
  51. Tyranno occiso quinque ejus proximes cognatione magistratus necato, Cic. de Invent. lib. 2.
  52. Book 8, p. 547.
  53. The anther of the Continuation of Rapin Thoyras defines A Bill of Attainder, a sentence which upon being approved by the two houses and signed by the king passes into an act. whereby the party accused is declared guilty of high treason without any other formality, without appeaal, Tom. 2. p. 266.
  54. Legem de singuhri aliquo ne rogato nisi sex millibus ita visum. Ex Andocide de Mysteriis. This is what they called Ostracism.
  55. De privis hominibus latæ, Cieero de Leg. lib 3.
  56. Scitum est jussum in omnes, Cicero ibid.
  57. See Philostratus book 1. Lives of the Sophists, life of Æschines. See likewise Plutarch and Phocius.
  58. By the Remmian Law.
  59. Plutarch in a treatise entitled. How a person may reap advantage from his enemies.
  60. A great many sold their children to pay their debts. Plutarch, life of Solon.
  61. Plutarch, life of Solon.
  62. It appears from history that this custom was established among the Romans before the law of the twelve tables. Livy I. dec. book 2.
  63. 'Dionys. Halicarn. Rom. Antiq. book VI.
  64. Plutarch, life of Furius Camillus.
  65. See what follows in the 24th chapter of the book of laws as relative to the use of money.
  66. One hundred and twenty years after the law of the twelve tables, eo anno plebi Romanæ, velut aliud initium libertatis factum est quod necti desierunt. Livy lib. 8.
  67. Bona debitoris, non corpus obnoxium esset. Ibid.
  68. The year of Rome 465.
  69. That of Plautius who made an attempt upon the body of Veturius; Valerius Maximus book 6 art 9. These two events ought not to be confunded; they are neither same persons, nor the same times.
  70. See a fragment of Dionys. Halicarn. in the extract of virtues and vices, Livy's epitome, book 2. & Freinshemius, book 2.
  71. Plutarch's Morals, Comparison of some Roman and Greek Histories, tom. 2. p. 487.
  72. Leg. VI. Cod. Theod. de Fam. Libellis.
  73. Nerva, says Tacitus, encreased the ease of the empire.
  74. State of Russia. p. 173. Paris edition, 1717.
  75. The Caliphs.
  76. History of the Tartars, 3d part p. 277. in the remarks.
  77. See Francis Pirard.
  78. As at present in Persia, according to Sir John Chardin; this custom is very ancient. They put Cavades, says Procopius, in the castle of oblivion; there is a law which forbids any one to speak of those who are shut up, or even to mention their name.
  79. The fifth law in the cod. ad leg. Jul. Maj.
  80. In the 8th chapter of this book.
  81. Frederic copied this law in the constitutions of Naples, book 1.
  82. In monarchies there is generally a law which forbids those who are invested with public employments to go out of the kingdom without the prince's leave. This law ought to be established also in republics. Rut in those that have particular institutions the prohibition ought to be general, in order to prevent the introduction of foreign manners.